Ok

En poursuivant votre navigation sur ce site, vous acceptez l'utilisation de cookies. Ces derniers assurent le bon fonctionnement de nos services. En savoir plus.

mercredi, 23 janvier 2019

Fukuyama on Diversity

fukuyamla.jpg

Fukuyama on Diversity

Francis Fukuyama’s latest book Identity was written to forestall the rise of Right-wing identity politics, but, as I argued in “Fukuyama on Identity Politics [2],” the book is actually very useful to White Nationalists because it concedes a number of our basic premises while offering weak reasons to resist our ultimate political conclusions. This is especially apparent in his discussion of diversity.

Diversity within the Same Society Causes Conflict

One of Fukuyama’s most useful concessions is that diversity within the same state causes conflict. He opens chapter 12, “We the People,” with an account of how Syria—a racially homogeneous society with significant ethnic and religious diversity—descended into a devastating civil war in 2011.

Let’s bracket the role of US intervention in kicking off the Syrian civil war, since outside forces were only exploiting existing fault lines. Instead, let’s just ask—given that religious and ethnic diversity caused Syria to descend into war—how is the much greater religious, ethnic, and racial diversity of America a strength?

It is a good question, to which Fukuyama offers four remarkably weak answers.

Fukuyama’s first reason for making one’s homeland more like Yugoslavia is the throwaway claim that “Exposure to different ways of thinking and acting can often stimulate innovation, creativity, and entrepreneurship” (p. 126). Of course we can expose ourselves to different ways of thinking and acting without changing the ethnic compositions of our societies. Furthermore, how much of this alleged innovation, creativity, and entrepreneurship is due to handling the problems of diversity? After all, you can stimulate economic activity by breaking windows. Increasing ethnic diversity certainly stimulates the market for CCTVs, window bars, pepper spray, car alarms, concrete barriers, and morning after pills. But those aren’t good things.

Fukuyama’s second reason to increase the risk of a Syrian-style civil war is all the great restaurants. No, I am not kidding:

Diversity provides interest and excitement. In the year 1970, Washington D.C. was a rather boring biracial city in which the most exotic food one would dine on was served at the Yenching Palace on Connecticut Avenue. Today, the greater Washington area is home to an incredible amount of ethnic diversity: one can get Ethiopian, Peruvian, Cambodian, and Pakistani food and travel from one small ethnic enclave to another. The internationalization of the city has stimulated other forms of interest: as it becomes a place where young people want to live, they bring new music, arts, technologies, and entire neighborhoods that didn’t exist before. (p. 127)

Where to begin?

First, to say that Washington DC in 1970 was a rather boring biracial city is to snobbishly denigrate both the black and white populations of the city, who—when they weren’t clashing with one another—found it a nice place to live. (Presumably the whites who could not economically segregate themselves from blacks were pretty well gone by then.)

Second, since when is the presence of ethnic restaurants an index of social well-being—as opposed, say, to social trust, neighborliness, and other values that Robert Putnam found decline as diversity increases?[1] [3]

Third, what percentage of non-whites run ethnic restaurants? Is it even 1%? I would gladly allow them to stay if we could deport the rest. But even better, if there is such a crying need for shawarma, why not learn to cook it ourselves?

Fourth, who are these young rootless cosmopolitan urbanites we are supposed to prize? Basically, they are Jews and people who think and live like them. But why should their preferences trump those of “boring” white (and black) people with families and jobs and communities?

And those “entire neighborhoods that didn’t exist before,” actually did exist before. At first they were occupied by white people, who were displaced by black riots and crime. Then they were occupied by blacks, who were displaced by hipsters driving up rents and calling in the police to enforce their preferred standards of behavior.

Diversity, in short, is not progress for all. Diversity is just a euphemism for fewer white people, especially “boring” white people who have families and yards but often lack tattoos and a taste for micro-brews. Do you really think these people won’t eventually start fighting back against their ethnic displacement?

FF-1.jpgThe third reason Fukuyama gives for emulating the Star Wars cantina comes from biology. Diversity, he informs us, is “crucial to [biological] resilience” and “the motor of evolution itself.” Amazingly, Fukuyama does not see that this is actually an argument for racial and cultural homogeneity and separatism. For when two distinct species occupy the same ecological niche, the result is the destruction of biological diversity through extinction or hybridization. If human biological and cultural diversity are values, then ethnonationalism follows as a matter of course, for ethnonationalism creates barriers to the chief causes of biological extinction, namely habitat loss, competition from invasive species, hybridization, and predation.

Fukuyama’s fourth reason for becoming more like Rwanda is that diversity is valuable because immigrants “resent being homogenized into larger cultures” and “want to hold on to the world’s fast-disappearing indigenous languages, and traditional practices that recall earlier ways of life” (p. 127).

There are several problems with this point. First, it is not an argument for why increased diversity is good for the natives of a society. How is America a better place by being more accommodating to immigrants who refuse to assimilate our customs and language? Second, if immigrants want to preserve their languages and customs, they should simply stay in their homelands. If they want to move to another country, shouldn’t they have to bear the cost of assimilation rather than impose the burden of unassimilated immigrants on their new society? Third, Fukuyama himself recommends imposing assimilationist policies two chapters later. So in what sense does he regard this sort of diversity as a value at all?

Fukuyama’s arguments for diversity are so weak, one has to wonder if he is even sincere. This impression is underscored by the fact that as soon as he offers his final argument (which he takes back later), he declares, “On the other hand, diversity is not an unalloyed good. Syria and Afghanistan are very diverse places, but such diversity yields violence and conflict rather than creativity and resilience” (pp. 127–28). National unity, he claims, has gotten a bad reputation “because it came to be associated with an exclusive, ethnically based sense of belonging known as ethno-nationalism” (p. 128). But there is nothing wrong with national identity as such, only “narrow, ethnically based, intolerant, aggressive, and deeply illiberal” forms of national identity. But, Fukuyama assures us, “National identities can be built around liberal and democratic political values” (p. 128).

Fukuyama then offers six arguments for the goodness of national unity.

First, it promotes physical security, as opposed to civil war and ethnic cleansing.

Second, it promotes just government as opposed to corrupt and factional government.

Third, it facilitates economic development.

Fourth, it promotes a wide range of social trust, which is an important factor in ensuring honest government and economic flourishing.

Fifth, it makes possible the welfare state. People are willing to pay high taxes if they think they are doing it for themselves, not for parasitic out groups. This is one reason why the United States did not develop as extensive a welfare state as Scandinavia or even Canada next door. The US has a large non-white population, and dark skin has proved to be a reliable marker of those who take more from the state than they contribute. Thus we can predict that rising non-white populations in Europe and elsewhere will lead to the decline of the welfare state.

Finally, national unity makes possible liberal democracy—and all forms of self-government, really—since without unity people do not feel that they are governing themselves. Instead, some groups inevitably feel they are being governed—and exploited—by other groups. For there to be pluralistic democracy without civil war, the different parties have to believe that they are fundamentally part of the same people. People are willing to trade power with other factions only if they do not feel they are being subjugated by an alien people.

All of these arguments have merit. But one has to ask: in what sort of society are they most likely to actually pertain, a society in which there is one race and one culture—or a multiracial, multicultural society where people share a democratic creed and culture? Genetic Similarity theory would predict the former, and the empirical studies of Robert Putnam and Tatu Vanhanen bear this out.

FF2.jpgPutnam studied 41 communities in the United States, ranging from highly diverse to highly homogeneous, and found that social trust was strongly correlated with homogeneity and social distrust with diversity. Putnam eliminated other possible causes for variations in social trust and concluded that “diversity per se has a major effect.”[2] [4] The loss of social trust leads to the decline of social order. People feel isolated, alienated, and powerless. They are less trusting of social institutions and strangers and less likely to be altruistic.

Vanhanen arrived at similar conclusions from a comparative study of diversity and conflict in 148 countries.[3] [5] Vanhanen found that whether they are rich or poor, democratic or authoritarian, diverse societies have more conflict than homogeneous societies, which are more harmonious, regardless of levels of wealth or democratization.

The Limits of Creedal Nationalism

Another remarkable concession that Fukuyama makes is that merely sharing the same creed is not enough to politically unify a society. National identity is not based on reason but on thumos. People have to passionately identify with their society:

. . . democracies will not survive if citizens are not in some measure irrationally attached to the ideas of constitutional government and human equality through feelings of pride and patriotism. These attachments will see societies through their low points, when reason alone may counsel despair at the working of institutions. (p. 131)

This explains a lot of the White Nationalist frustration with the post-World War II “Baby Boom” Generation. Boomer conservatives are highly resistant to White Nationalist arguments simply because their attachment to color-blind conservative civic nationalism was never based on arguments. Instead, it is based on a passionate thumotic identification with an America that is melting away before their very eyes—and they are remarkably blind to it.

This brings us to the fundamental White Nationalist objection to colorblind civic nationalism. Fukuyama wants all Americans to stop engaging in factional identity politics and instead identify with the whole of America, defined in maximally inclusive liberal democratic terms. But American civic nationalism is not a workable political ideology, because it will only be adopted by whites. Non-whites will continue openly or covertly to practice identity politics, because it benefits them.

Team strategies consistently outperform individualist strategies. Thus if whites practice color-blind individualism while non-whites practice racial and ethnic collectivism, whites will steadily lose wealth and power to non-whites. Thus, in practice, color-blind civic nationalism is simply a mechanism of white dispossession—a mechanism that blinds whites to what is happening and teaches them that blindness is a moral virtue. If you preach blindness as a moral virtue, chances are you are up to no good.

Our people’s irrational identification with American civic nationalism is a huge impediment to White Nationalism. But on balance, thumos works in our favor, because attachments to family, ethnicity, and race are far more concrete and real than attachments to an increasingly polarized and dysfunctional empire and its threadbare ideology.

Thus the best way to deprogram our people is to use thumos against itself by systematically confronting them with how their loyalty to the imperial ideology clashes with their more concrete and natural loyalties. Nothing brings home the moral obscenity of liberal civic nationalism quite like the reactions of the Tibbetts family of Iowa [6] to the murder of their daughter by an illegal alien. Some people are willing to pay quite a lot for authentic burritos.

Liberal Democratic Theory Undermines National Identities

Yet another useful concession to White Nationalism is Fukuyama’s admission that liberal democratic theory undermines national identities. This problem is brought home by the problem of immigration, which is one of the primary forces driving people toward National Populism. Fukuyama concedes that this backlash is essentially reasonable, since levels of migration are at historic highs in America, which has a long history of immigration, and Europe, which does not.

But then Fukuyama offers a stunningly dishonest rejoinder to the white Americans who want to “take back” their country. The US Constitution, he says, establishes a particular political order for “ourselves and our Posterity.” “But it does not define who the people are, or on what basis individuals are to be included in the national community” (p. 133). In fact, the Constitution makes it pretty clear who “ourselves and our posterity” are. Blacks and American Indians are not considered part of the American polity. And in 1790, when the Founders turned their attention to who they were willing to “naturalize” and allow to mix with their posterity, they specified that they be “free white people.”

Thus many white Americans correctly believe that a white republic is their birthright, a birthright that has been long eroded and is now on the brink of being wrested away from them irrevocably. Again, does anyone really believe that white Americans would not start resisting their dispossession once the endgame became clear?

Nonetheless, Fukuyama is correct to point out—citing fellow neocon Pierre Manent—that liberal theory simply assumes the existence of nation-states. Moreover, because liberalism is based on the idea of universal human rights, which prescind from ethnic and racial differences, liberal theory cannot generate borders between states. Indeed, liberalism tends to undermine nation-states and promote global government.

Surprisingly, Fukuyama rejects global government because “no one has been able to come up with a good method for holding such bodies democratically accountable” (p. 138). Moreover, “The functioning of democratic institutions depends on shared norms, perspectives, and ultimately culture, all of which can exist on the level of a national state but which do not exist internationally” (p. 138). Thus Fukuyama concludes that international bodies must be based on the cooperation of sovereign states.

But this defense of the nation-state rings hollow when one recalls that Fukuyama recommends that nation-states make a commitment to liberal democracy central to their identity, which entails that eventually there will be no meaningful differences between them, anyway.

How to Create an Ethnostate

For me, the most remarkable concession that Fukuyama makes to White Nationalism is his discussion of how national identities are created.

First, we can keep borders constant and move people across them, removing existing populations and bringing in new ones.

Second, we can let people stay where they are and move borders to fit them.

These are, of course, the two mechanisms to create racially and ethnically homogeneous states.

Third, we can “assimilate minority populations into the culture of an existing ethnic or linguistic group” (p. 141).

Fourth, we can “reshape national identity to fit the existing characteristics of the society in question” (p. 141).

FF3.jpgThese are the mechanisms preferred by civic nationalists like Fukuyama.

Astonishingly, Fukuyama also grants that “All four of the paths to national identity can be accomplished peacefully and consensually, or through violence and coercion” (p. 142). Yes, Fukuyama is saying that we can create ethnostates by moving borders and peoples in a peaceful and consensual manner, without resorting to violence and coercion. Lest some peoples mount their high horse and lecture other peoples on their historical guilt, Fukuyama also adds that, “All existing nations are the historical by-product of some combination of the four and drew on some combination or coercion and consensus” (p. 142).

But then Fukuyama pulls a fast one:

The challenge facing contemporary liberal democracies in the face of immigration and growing diversity is to undertake some combination of the third and fourth paths—to define an inclusive national identity that fits the society’s diverse reality, and to assimilate newcomers to that identity. What is at stake in this task is the preservation of liberal democracy itself. (p. 143)

Later he writes:

We need to promote creedal national identities built around the foundational ideas of modern liberal democracy, and use public policies to deliberately assimilate newcomers to those identities. Liberal democracy has its own culture, which must be held in higher esteem than cultures rejecting democracy’s values. (p. 166)

First, note that Fukuyama is treating immigration and diversity simply as problems that must be managed. This is true. But since he has only given weak reasons to value diversity at all, why stop at merely managing it?

Why not reduce immigration and diversity dramatically—or eliminate them entirely? Why shouldn’t a society try to be less like Syria, Yugoslavia, or Rwanda? It is not clear whether Fukuyama ever envisions stopping additional diversity. Will there always be “newcomers”? Why?

Fukuyama has already pointed out that it is possible to create more homogeneous societies by moving borders and moving peoples in a completely moral manner, so why are the first two options simply passed over?

Later, Fukuyama writes:

The question is not whether Americans should go backward into an ethnic and religious understanding of identity. The contemporary fate of the United States—and that of any other culturally diverse democracy that wants to survive—is to be a creedal nation. (p. 161)

No, America is not “fated” to be a multicultural society. Nor is Sweden, France, or any other white society. It was not “fate” that opened our borders and deconstructed white norms and cultures in favor of multiculturalism. It was men who decided on this experiment in social engineering, and it was men wielding the tools of statecraft and propaganda that forced it upon white societies.

These decisions can, moreover, be reversed by other, better men, and the consequences can be undone by the same tools. If it is possible for immigrants to enter white countries, it is possible for them to leave the same way. So the question really is whether white countries should want to restore themselves. Because where there’s a will, there’s a way—a completely non-violent and humane way, according to Fukuyama.

Multiculturalism is a program of social engineering that was only imposed on most white countries in the decades following the Second World War. The consequences, moreover, have been catastrophic—and they only get worse with time. For instance, second generation Muslim immigrants are more of a problem than their parents. Why should this recent experiment in social engineering—an experiment that has failed as badly as Communism—be treated as sacrosanct? Beware of Hegelians talking about “fate.”

For White Nationalists, it is not a question of wanting to “survive” as a “culturally diverse democracy.” We wish, first and foremost, to survive as a race and as distinct white nations, and we believe that white survival is not compatible with racially and ethnically diverse democracies. As I argue in The White Nationalist Manifesto [7], multicultural liberal democracy is subjecting the white race in all of our homelands to conditions that will lead to our biological and cultural extinction [8]—unless White Nationalism turns these trends around. Compared to extinction, every other political issue that divides us pales into insignificance.

Fukuyama does not address the question of whether multicultural, multiracial liberal democracies are consistent with the long-term survival of whites. And he offers no good reason for why whites should not seek to restore or create homogeneous homelands. Instead, he merely offers proposals on how to make multiracial liberal democracies work better, in order to forestall the rise of Right-wing populism. However, as we shall see in the final installment of this series [9], his proposals are astonishingly weak.

Notes

[1] [10] Robert D. Putnam, “E Pluribus Unum: Diversity and Community in the Twenty-First Century,” Scandinavian Political Studies, 30 (2007).

[2] [11] Ibid., p. 153.

[3] [12] Tatu Vanhanen, Ethnic Conflicts Explained by Ethnic Nepotism (Stamford, Conn.: JAI Press, 1999).

 

Article printed from Counter-Currents Publishing: https://www.counter-currents.com

URL to article: https://www.counter-currents.com/2019/01/fukuyama-on-diversity/

URLs in this post:

[1] Image: https://www.counter-currents.com/wp-content/uploads/2019/01/Fuku2.jpg

[2] Fukuyama on Identity Politics: https://www.counter-currents.com/2019/01/fukuyama-on-identity-politics/

[3] [1]: #_ftn1

[4] [2]: #_ftn2

[5] [3]: #_ftn3

[6] the Tibbetts family of Iowa: https://www.counter-currents.com/2019/01/the-pathological-altruism-of-the-tibbetts-family/

[7] The White Nationalist Manifesto: https://www.counter-currents.com/product/the-white-nationalist-manifesto/

[8] biological and cultural extinction: https://www.counter-currents.com/2017/06/white-extinction-2/

[9] the final installment of this series: https://www.counter-currents.com/2019/01/fukuyama-on-civic-nationalism/

[10] [1]: #_ftnref1

[11] [2]: #_ftnref2

[12] [3]: #_ftnref3

 

Fukuyama on Civic Nationalism

fukuid.jpg

Fukuyama on Civic Nationalism

In his new book Identity, Francis Fukuyama seeks to forestall the rise of white identity politics. Nevertheless, as I argue in “Fukuyama on Identity Politics [2],” Identity is a very useful book for White Nationalists because it concedes many of our most important premises. In “Fukuyama on Diversity [3],” I argue that Fukuyama admits that diversity is a problem and offers only very weak reasons to value it at all. Here I examine Fukuyama’s alternative to white identity politics, namely a conservative form of color-blind civic nationalism. 

Making the European Union Work

Fukuyama focuses on the European Union rather than individual European states because he clearly wants to make the EU work.

The EU, he says, was created because “exclusive ethnic definitions of national identity had been at the root of the two world wars that Europe experienced” (p. 143). “The founders of the European Union deliberately sought to weaken national identities at the member-state level in favor of a ‘postnational’ European consciousness, as an antidote to the aggressive ethno-nationalism of the first half of the twentieth century” (p. 143).

It is astonishing that the modern EU project is founded on an almost perfect inversion of historical truth. The First World War was not a clash of ethnostates but of Empires: the British, French, and Russian vs. the German, Austro-Hungarian, and Ottoman Empires. The war broke out because of the Austro-Hungarian Empire’s clash with the kingdom of Serbia—itself a multinational state—over the multinational territory of Bosnia, as they scrambled to divide the carcass of the multinational Ottoman Empire in the Balkans. The entire war could have been avoided, though, if ethnonationalism rather than imperialism had been the guiding policy of Europe, moving borders and people to create homogeneous sovereign homelands for all peoples.

The Second World War could have been avoided in the same way if, in the aftermath of the First World War, the principle of national self-determination had been actually practiced as opposed to merely preached. But instead of dividing multiethnic empires into homogeneous states wherever possible, the victors divided countries like Germany and Hungary and created new multiethnic states like Czechoslovakia and Yugoslavia.

The European Union, in short, is built on lies. The World Wars were not caused by nationalism. They were caused by the suppression of the legitimate nationalist aspirations of European peoples by multinational imperial bodies—just like the European Union.

How does Fukuyama propose to make the EU work? According to Fukuyama, the main failures of the EU were (1) not creating a “strong sense of pan-European identity that supersedes the identities of its member states” (p. 153) and (2) not creating “democratic accountability” which left the citizens of EU states feeling “little sense of ownership or control over the institutions governing Europe as a whole” (p. 144). Thus the solution is to intensify the EU’s existing drive to destroy the national identities of the member states, but to make the process more democratic, so the technocrats can tell protesters that “You are doing it to ourselves.” (Of course this democracy would have to be a sham, otherwise Europeans will vote to stop the destruction of their homelands.) As Fukuyama puts it:

The European agenda must start with redefinitions of national identity embodied in its citizenship laws. Ideally, the EU should create a single citizenship whose requirements would be based on adherence to basic liberal democratic principles, one that would supersede national citizenship laws. . . . It would help if the EU democratized itself by shifting powers from the Commission to the Parliament and tried to make up for lost time by investing in European identity through the creation of appropriate symbols and narratives that would be inculcated through a common educational system. . . . Those laws of EU member states still based on jus sanguinis [the right of blood, i.e., citizenship through descent] need to be changed to jus soli [the right of soil, i.e., the idea that one has the right of citizenship simply by being born on a given country’s soil, what Vox Day mocks as “magic dirt”] so as not to privilege one ethnic group over another. (p. 167)

Let’s pause for a minute, take a deep breath, and reflect on the strange decay of language that allows such overheated Jacobin fantasies to be called a form of conservatism.

These proposals, if adopted, would spell the death of the white race and all of its distinct nations in Europe. Every European nation has below-replacement levels of fertility. Redefining European identity in inclusive liberal democratic terms will lead inevitably to open borders. (Face it, that’s really the whole point in redefining European identity as openness.) Open borders and granting citizenship to anyone born within Europe’s territory will lead to the replacement of Europeans with non-Europeans within a few generations. Basically, for whites, liberal democratic openness amounts to openness to collective suicide. And Fukuyama proposes making openness to demographic annihilation the defining value of European identity.

Ironically, Fukuyama himself realizes that “diversity cannot be the basis for identity in and of itself; it is like saying that our identity is to have no identity . . .” (p. 159). But making an identity of liberal democracy, defined as being essentially open to diversity, has the exact same problem. As a concept, it is vacuous, and when put into practice it can lead only to destruction.

But won’t our replacements be “Europeans” if they are assimilated to the new European identity—which is to be maximally open to demographic replacement? Of course not.

First of all, it might be the case that only white people are stupid enough to adopt a collective suicide pact as an identity.

Second, why would any healthy population wish to emulate the value system of a race that built the richest civilization in world history—then went mad and gave it all away?

Third, it would be far more advantageous for immigrant populations to merely pretend to accept liberal democratic openness while practicing strict preferences for their own tribes. Liberal democratic true believers would blind themselves to this form of cheating, so there is little danger of being found out and punished. And even if cheaters were caught, liberals would just blame themselves (or retrograde xenophobic whites) for failing to be sufficiently open.

Fourth, Fukuyama envisions a democratized European Union, which means that once the white population is too small and weak to maintain the hegemony of its suicidal value system, the newcomers will simply vote to replace it with something more to their liking, most probably an Islamic state. It is the height of naivete to think that once non-whites are the majority, they will continue to take orders from white liberals.

Fukuyama has a few specific proposals for EU member states. He praises Emanuel Macron trying to break France’s unions and “liberalize” its labor laws to make it possible for more blacks and Muslims to find jobs (p. 172). In short, migrant employment should be paid for by falling French wages and living standards.

He also suggests destroying the Dutch system of state-supported parochial schools and replacing it with a single state education system with a standardized curriculum of liberal democratic swill—again, to better integrate Muslims (pp. 151, 171). As if Dutch schoolboys and schoolgirls don’t have enough problems with Muslim youths outside of school hours.

These are very real threats to the well-being of countless Europeans. Yet Fukuyama airily reassures us that “The region [a sinisterly generic term for Europe] is not threatened by immigrants so much as by the political reaction that immigrants and cultural diversity create” (p. 153). In fact, the deepest threat to Europe is liberal democracy. The pauperization of French workers; the bullying and rape of Dutch schoolchildren; the Bataclan massacre, the Nice massacre, and countless other terrorist attacks on European soil—these events do not threaten the plans of people like Fukuyama and the EU leadership. Pauperization, cultural annihilation, and race replacement are parts of the plan. They are small prices  to pay — for other people to pay — for the realization of the European Dream. What threatens the EU is Europeans awakening to the fact that the EU’s dream is their nightmare, then rejecting their destruction.

Are any of Fukuyama’s suggestions likely to be adopted? Of course not. Even the most Left-wing and ethnomasochist EU member states would reject these schemes. To his credit, Fukuyama himself recognizes that his proposals have no realistic chance of being implemented by the EU. At best, they can only be implemented by particular member states. Which means on his own terms that liberal democracies will be increasingly polarized between identity politics of the Left and the Right. Fukuyama warns that, “Down this road lies, ultimately, state breakdown and failure” (p. 165).

But the breakdown and failure Fukuyama envision is of multicultural, multiracial liberal democracies that do not adopt assimilationism and the construction of a liberal democratic “identity” to unify them. There is, however, another solution: the preservation, restoration, or creation of racially and ethnically homogeneous states by moving borders and people—and I will never tire of repeating that Fukuyama admits that these processes can be carried out in a wholly non-violent and ethical manner.

multiUS.jpg

Making Multicultural America Work

Fukuyama’s proposals for making a multicultural America work are no more plausible. Basically, he argues for a “liberal democratic” multicultural civic nationalism, which consists of a creed and a minimally “Protestant” culture. First the creed:

[The] creedal understanding of American identity emerged as the result of a long struggle stretching over nearly two centuries and represented a decisive break with earlier versions of identity based on race, ethnicity, or religion. Americans can be proud of this very substantive identity; it is based on belief in the common political principles of constitutionalism, the rule of law, democratic accountability, and the principle that “all men are created equal” (now interpreted to include all women). These political ideas come directly out of the Enlightenment and are the only possible basis for unifying a modern liberal democracy that has become de facto multicultural. (p. 158)

Fukuyama deserves praise for conceding that the “creedal” civic nationalist concept of American identity was contested from the start and only became dominant in the 20th century—in fact in the 1960s with the success of the black civil rights movement and the abandonment of America’s immigration laws that aimed at maintaining a white supermajority.

Fukuyama argues that a creedal identity is not enough. It is a necessary condition to make a multicultural liberal democracy work. But it is not a sufficient condition. The other necessary condition is . . . a common culture, including a set of virtues. But this common culture has to be vacuous enough to somehow include multiculturalism, and it has to be detached from any fixed biological categories like race and, I presume, sex. Fukuyama’s answer is the Anglo-Protestant culture, stripped of anything exclusively Anglo and Protestant, i.e., retaining only those aspects of Anglo-Protestant identity that make it a collective suicide pact.

The only specific Anglo-Protestant virtue that Fukuyama mentions is, of course, the “work ethic.” Americans, after all, work hard. Not as hard as Asians, Fukuyama reminds us, but certainly harder than those effete Europeans. Americans respect hard work and economic competition (and low wages) so much that we have repeatedly debased the ethnic homogeneity of our society to bring in hard-working and cheap (or just plain cheap) immigrants. And if white Americans are displaced by non-white immigrants, well that’s fair. You didn’t mistake this economic zone for a homeland did you?

In the end, there’s nothing specifically Anglo or Protestant about the economy. As producers and consumers, we are all fungible. Who works hard in America these days? Fukuyama’s answer is: “It is just as likely to be a Korean grocery-store owner or an Ethiopian cab-driver or a Mexican gardener as a person of Anglo-Protestant heritage living off dividends in his or her country club” (p. 161).

This point is problematic in a number of ways.

First, it proves too much, for if there’s nothing specifically Anglo-Protestant about the marketplace, there is nothing specifically American about it either. The market and its virtues are global. Thus in what sense are we talking about anything American at all?

Second, the proper reaction of an American identitarian to this concept of identity is simply to reject it. We reject any universal, non-exclusive identity that makes all men fungible. The whole point of a national identity is to be exclusive. The whole point of a homeland is to enjoy it as a birthright and to pass it on to one’s posterity—and only one’s posterity. The whole point of a homeland is that it belongs to us, and we belong to it, unconditionally. We don’t have to earn it. We don’t have to compete with foreigners to keep it. Why shouldn’t Americans have that kind of homeland, that kind of security—especially if we do not begrudge others the right to their own homelands?

The only reason anyone will ask you to replace an exclusive form of national identity with an inclusive one is because he envisions replacing you in your homeland. Once you define yourself as replaceable, someone will replace you.

Third, to claim that a Korean, an Ethiopian, a Mexican, and a WASP are “just as likely” to be hard-working is implicitly to reject biological race differences and to embrace social constructivism, which Fukuyama hints at elsewhere. But biological race differences are real, which means that taken at random, WASPs and Koreans are far more likely than Mexicans and Ethiopians to be successful in the American economic system. And Fukuyama implicitly recognizes this, since if race did not matter, why is his hypothetical Korean not a gardener and his hypothetical Mexican not a grocery-store owner?

Finally, note the lazy, sloppy language. No WASP “lives off dividends in his or her country club.” Nobody lives in country clubs at all. This anti-WASP canard has become so hackneyed that people can’t even be bothered to make it sound plausible.

Will Fukuyama’s proposals save liberal democracy in America? The answer is no.

First of all, although Fukuyama advertises his book as an attempt to stave off Trumpian identity politics, his outlook and policy proposals are essentially indistinguishable from Trumpian civic nationalism. So liberal democrats will simply reject Identity as a disingenuous attempt to advance Trumpism while bashing Trump.

Second, demanding that immigrants assimilate, even to an almost vacuous liberal creed and Protestant culture, is still “racism” and “cultural imperialism” as far as the Left is concerned. Is Fukuyama really going to challenge the taboo against racism? I doubt he is willing to pay that price, which means that his proposals are a dead letter.

White Nationalists, by contrast, have no problem taking heat for “racism”: we unapologetically take our own side in ethnic conflicts. We aim to create or restore white homelands by moving people and borders. But we have no desire to assimilate non-whites—or be assimilated by them. We simply want to go our separate ways. That’s the whole point of having separate homelands where different peoples can practice different ways of life without outside interference.

Third, even if Fukuyama’s ideas were adopted, they would not be enough to save America from white identity politics. White identity politics is not simply being driven by Left identity politics, so that if one turned off Left identity politics, white identity politics would dry up. Rather, white identity politics is being driven by one of the consequences of Left identity politics, namely white dispossession. But even if the Left halted identity politics, white dispossession is still “baked in” to Fukuyama’s scheme, since the borders would remain open, white birthrates would remain low, and non-white birthrates would remain high. But as the white majority continues to decline, white ethnocentrism will continue to rise, feeding white identity politics.

Fourth, even if we implemented all of Fukuyama’s policies, only whites are likely to actually believe in and practice multicultural civic nationalism—because only whites do so today. There is nothing in Fukuyama’s plan to prevent non-whites from cheating: outwardly professing liberal democratic universalism and demanding to be treated accordingly, while covertly practicing preferences for their own tribes. Thus Fukuyama’s solution would simply intensify the ongoing process of white dispossession. At best it might slow down the backlash, by blinding people to what is happening. But it might also ensure that the backlash is far more severe when it actually arrives.

In their hearts, I think many civic nationalists believe that America and Europe took a wrong turn when they opened their borders and embraced diversity. But they are unwilling to contemplate actually rolling back the Left’s social engineering, specifically the catastrophic demographic and cultural trends of the last half-century. It is a gigantic failure of imagination and nerve.

For example, consider Fukuyama’s comments on the millions of illegal aliens in America:

It is . . . ridiculous to think that the United States could ever force all these people to leave the country and return to their countries of origin. A project on that scale would be worthy of Stalin’s Soviet Union or Nazi Germany. (p. 176)

First, if it is possible for people to enter the United States, it is possible for them to leave. What’s truly ridiculous is thinking that the turnstile at the border only turns one way. Second, the United States has forced millions of Mexicans to return to Mexico twice in the 20th century, and in neither case did it turn into genocide. (We need a wall, so we don’t have the deport them a fourth time.) Third, didn’t Fukuyama himself, on page 142 of the very same book, claim that ethnic cleansing can take place in an entirely non-violent and ethical fashion?

Because of this failure of nerve and imagination, writers like Fukuyama are driven to the makeshift ideology of “liberal democratic” multicultural civic nationalism. If you believe that Leftism and diversity are destroying civilization, but you are too scared to contemplate actually reversing the damage, your only hope is to halt the decline by imposing a sham unity on ethnic diversity—by synthesizing an inclusive creed and culture, then demanding people assimilate it.

Another reason why a color-blind civic nationalism appeals to Fukuyama is simply because he is not white. No matter how convinced he might be that multiculturalism and immigration have catastrophic consequences, he will never contemplate an alternative that does secure his presence and upward mobility.

To defeat civic nationalists like Fukuyama, we must not only demonstrate that their solutions are unworkable, but also show that the creation of racially and ethnically homogeneous homelands is both moral and practical. The Left is destroying white civilization, and neocons like Fukuyama can’t save it. It is time for them to step aside and let ethnonationalists take over.

Afterthoughts

Fukuyama makes three other noteworthy points that are useful to White Nationalists.

First, he argues that dual citizenship is a “rather questionable practice” if “one takes national identity seriously.” “Different nations have different interests that can engender potentially conflicting allegiances” (p. 168). I don’t know what percentage of neocons have dual US-Israeli citizenships, but it is certainly above the national average, and Fukuyama knows it. So this is a rather gutsy position to take.

Second, Fukuyama points out a crucially important distinction that globalists stubbornly refuse to acknowledge, namely the distinction between human rights and civil rights (pp. 173-74). Human rights are universal. Civil rights are particular. We are morally obligated to respect the human rights of all people. We are not morally obligated to give civil rights to all people. Ethnonationalists can recognize that all people have basic human rights, but we can still say that they are not good fits for our particular societies.

Third, Fukuyama points out an important implication of the distinction between human rights and civil rights (p. 175). We all have human rights, but simply having human rights does not entitle us to enter other people’s countries and demand to participate in their political life, which is what civil rights entitle us to do. Nations still have the right to control their borders and determine who may and may not become “naturalized” parts of their body politic.

One human right that we need to respect is the right of refugees to safe harbor. After all, any people can suffer misfortune. (Although obviously dumber and more quarrelsome peoples are more “accident prone” than others.) But the United Nations has already drawn up reasonable laws about refugees. A refugee has the right to take refuge in the closest safe country, for instance Syrians fleeing to Turkey or Lebanon. (This makes sense in terms of moral reciprocity, given that in different circumstances, Turks and Lebanese might wish to take refuge in Syria.) But once a person leaves the closest safe place for better pay and benefits, he is no longer a refugee, he is a migrant, and other countries have the absolute right to bar his entry.

Afterword

Identity is a poorly written book. It is repetitive, padded, and poorly organized. There are also a number of places where I actually laughed out loud. To end on a light note, I will share a few.

In his Preface, Fukuyama writes: “Megalothymia thrives on exceptionality: taking big risks, engaging in monumental struggles, seeking large effects, because all these lead to recognition of oneself as superior to others. In some cases, it can lead to a heroic leader like a Lincoln or a Churchill or a Nelson Mandela. But in other cases it can lead to tyrants like Caesar or Hitler or Mao who lead their societies into dictatorship and disaster” (pp. xiii-xiv).

On page 34, Fukuyama writes: “Rousseau’s assertion that pride emerged only at a certain stage of social evolution is curious; it begs the question of how such an intrinsic human feeling could spontaneously appear in response to an external stimulus.” “Begs the question” refers to a logical fallacy, which is clearly inapplicable here. Fukuyama means “raises the question.” This is a very common error in spoken English, but it seldom gets into books by reputable publishers.

On page 70, Fukuyama writes of jihadis: “When they showed up in Syria with a long beard and toting an AK-47 or staged a murderous attack on their fellow Europeans, their families always professed surprise and incomprehension at the transformation.” First, most jihadis carry American-made weapons. Second, “fellow Europeans.” Third, taking Muslim professions of surprise and incomprehension at face value when their religion teaches them to lie to infidels as a weapon of jihad.

But the best laugh appears on page 176: “. . . the United States now hosts a population of 11–12 million undocumented aliens. . . . The idea that they are all criminals because they violated U.S. law to enter the country is ridiculous.” If you are ever on trial, you should suggest that your lawyer use Fukuyama’s argument: “Your honor, the idea that my client is a criminal just because he violated the law is ridiculous.”

 

Article printed from Counter-Currents Publishing: https://www.counter-currents.com

URL to article: https://www.counter-currents.com/2019/01/fukuyama-on-civic-nationalism/

URLs in this post:

[1] Image: https://www.counter-currents.com/wp-content/uploads/2019/01/IdentityUS.jpg

[2] Fukuyama on Identity Politics: https://www.counter-currents.com/2019/01/fukuyama-on-identity-politics/

[3] Fukuyama on Diversity: https://www.counter-currents.com/2019/01/fukuyama-on-diversity/

Le progressisme sociétal est au service des intérêts sociaux-économiques du Système !

multisociétal.jpg

Le progressisme sociétal est au service des intérêts sociaux-économiques du Système !

par Antonin Campana

Ex: http://www.autochtonisme.com

On sait, depuis Gramsci, que tous les systèmes de domination reposent sur un pouvoir culturel. Le système de domination oligarchique, quant à lui, passe par une suprématie culturelle mais aussi par un suprémacisme sociétal, un suprémacisme qui s’affirme peu à peu dès 1789 et qui, aujourd’hui, n’est quasiment plus contesté, si ce n’est par quelques milieux réfractaires.

Le processus d’hégémonie culturelle est quasiment arrivé à son point terminal : les individus fréquentent davantage les centres commerciaux que les églises, ils cherchent moins à préserver leur liberté que leur « pouvoir d’achat », ils se soucient de leur individualité mais pas de leur lignée, ils ont conscience de leurs intérêts mais ignorent leur communauté, ils croient être libres mais sont domestiqués. L’homme d’aujourd’hui  est laid (au propre comme au figuré), déstructuré, liquide, superficiel, ignorant, égoïste et moralement tout petit. Même son QI semble s’amenuiser d’année en année, c’est dire ! Cette réalité, à peine caricaturée, prouve que le Système maîtrise à son profit et depuis longtemps tous les outils qui lui permettent d’assurer son hégémonie culturelle (enseignement scolaire, intelligentsia, télévision, presse, production artistique, publicité…). Cela prouve aussi qu’il en use pour amoindrir l’humain, ce qui devrait enlever toute illusion à son sujet. 

Il est évident que cette hégémonie culturelle sert les intérêts du Système. L’Eglise, l’idée nationale, la capacité à penser selon des valeurs constituent autant de frontières morales, physiques ou intellectuelles qui parasitent la relation à la marchandise, qui entravent la libre circulation des biens, des capitaux et des hommes, voire qui limitent la consommation des produits et détournent l’attention des préoccupations strictement matérielles et monnayables, seules légitimes. Un croyant, un patriote, ou un individu dépositaire de l’héritage d’une lignée, ne sera jamais pleinement un consommateur. Il y a quelque chose en lui qui échappe au Système, un quant-à-soi dangereux que celui-ci ne peut marchandiser et qui doit donc être détruit.

L’hégémonie culturelle du Système transforme les individus en consommateurs accomplis. Plus rien ne subsiste en eux que le désir d’exister à travers les produits qu’ils achètent et l’argent qu’ils gagnent. Toutefois, pour avoir une efficacité maximum, cette hégémonie culturelle doit aussi devenir sociétale. Autrement dit, elle doit pénétrer les mœurs et dicter les relations entre les hommes.

Prenons l’exemple des rôles sociaux masculins et féminins. Ces rôles sociaux, que l’on sait largement dictés par la nature, ont aussi une indéniable dimension culturelle (c’est pourquoi ces rôles peuvent varier d’une société à l’autre, voyez l’islam, sans qu’ils soient exactement les mêmes quelque part). On comprendra que du point de vue Système, cette différentiation des rôles sociaux entre les sexes constitue une perte importante d’énergie. Pourquoi les femmes resteraient-elles dans leur foyer pour éduquer leurs enfants ? Ne seraient-ils pas oligarchiquement plus rentable de les mettre à l’usine avec des salaires moindres (dans un premier temps et pour faire baisser le coût du travail) et de leur faire payer dans le même mouvement  l’éducation oligarchique de leurs enfants ? Et puis, ne pourrait-on pas rentabiliser la « maternité », en marchandisant la PMA et en industrialisant la GPA par exemple ? Pour arriver à ses fins, le Système va accoucher du féminisme. Il va « libérer » les femmes en prétextant leur donner le même rôle social qu’aux hommes. Il va en fait exploiter leur force de travail, en attendant d’exploiter leur ventre. L’émancipation des femmes signifie, comme l’immigration, l’augmentation du nombre de consommateurs et de producteurs sous-payés. Et cela est bon pour les affaires.  

En fait, le Système conçoit l’organisation des populations humaines comme un éleveur de poulet conçoit son élevage en batterie. On sait que l’homogénéité est pour l’éleveur un facteur important de productivité. L’homogénéité de l’élevage permet d’assurer une meilleure gestion de l’alimentation, une meilleure évacuation des déjections, une stimulation lumineuse adaptée à tous les membres du groupe, une meilleure maîtrise de la concentration des animaux. L’homogénéité permet aussi d’endiguer le risque microbien, de standardiser le matériel de production ou d’envoyer à l’abattage tout le lot arrivé en même temps à maturité… Pour obtenir cette homogénéité, l’éleveur fait ce qu’on appelle un « calibrage » : en début de production, il pèse et isole les petits sujets afin que ceux-ci rattrapent leurs congénères par un meilleur accès à la mangeoire ou à l’abreuvoir. On peut renouveler l’opération si besoin est. L’objectif est d’obtenir à terme une homogénéité supérieure à 80%. La raison est triviale : gagner en productivité pour gagner plus d’argent.

De la même manière, le Système a intérêt à ce que les citoyens soit à 80% « sans distinction » (Constitution), c’est-à-dire « calibrés ». Il pourra ainsi soumettre les individus aux mêmes hiérarchies. Il pourra les affecter aux mêmes fonctions. Il pourra les manipuler en usant des mêmes émotions. Il pourra les grouper, les organiser, les redistribuer selon ses besoins et sans se soucier des anciennes incompatibilités naturelles, culturelles ou géographiques, désormais effacées. En rendant homogène le cheptel humain, le Système n’a plus à tenir compte des origines, des races, des sexes, des religions, des comportements sexuels… Pour le système d’exploitation, le calibrage représente donc indéniablement un gain important d’énergie, aussi important sans doute que dans un élevage de poulets en batterie. Bien sûr, le calibrage des hommes est bien plus subtil et beaucoup plus long que celui des poulets. Le métissage est un bon moyen d’évoluer vers le standard, de même que la substitution du « genre » aux sexes ou la confusion entretenue des rôles sociaux masculins et féminins. Il sera profitable aussi qu’un nouvel ordre sexuel basé sur l’union inconstante et superficielle entre individus abstraits et plus ou moins asexués se substitue à l’ordre sexuel traditionnel fondé sur l’union d’un homme et d’une femme en vue de fonder une famille.

Le progressisme sociétal (le féminisme, l’idéologie LGBT, l’antijaphétisme, le soutien aux minorités…) est donc un moyen du processus de calibrage de l’humain. Au nom de l’interchangeabilité planétaire et du calibrage institutionnalisé, il est important que tous les hommes soient passivement les clones d’un être qui ne serait plus vraiment Blanc ou Noir, homme ou femme, chrétien ou musulman, jeune ou vieux, hétérosexuel ou homosexuel… Le calibrage sociétal est la condition de la rentabilité maximum. Aussi faut-il que cesse le détournement inutile d’énergie au profit des appartenances traditionnelles : toute l’énergie humaine du cheptel doit bénéficier au système qui exploite le cheptel. Comprenez bien, au nom de l’efficacité du système d’exploitation, aucune fraction de cette énergie ne doit revenir inutilement au cheptel. La famille traditionnelle, l’ordre sexué, les traditions, les religions… sont des parasites du système d’exploitation, des parasites qu’il convient donc d’éradiquer. Le Système ne peut tolérer des mangeurs d’énergie qui accaparent en partie ce qui lui est du en totalité. Et peu importe que ce processus-Système de captation d’énergie, de vol !, transforme les peuples, vidés de leur âme, en troupeaux de zombies : c’est l’objectif de la manœuvre !

 En 1789, une classe de bourgeois et de marchands a pris le pouvoir. Cette classe oligarchique a taillé les institutions à sa mesure et depuis deux siècles n’a rien laissé au hasard pour perpétuer son emprise sur la société. Imaginer que des évolutions sociétales d’une importance historique inouïe, comme celles que nous vivons actuellement, puissent n’avoir pas été décidées et conduites par cette oligarchie relève, tant les faits sont évidents, d’un déni ridicule. Objectivement, ces évolutions sociétales servent les intérêts sociaux-économiques du régime oligarchique. Celui-ci a tout à craindre d’un peuple organisé et tout à profiter d’un agrégat sagement calibré.  

Antonin Campana

00:45 Publié dans Actualité, Sociologie | Lien permanent | Commentaires (0) | Tags : sociologie, progressisme sociétal, sociétal | |  del.icio.us | | Digg! Digg |  Facebook

Le RIC. Il faudra bien y venir en France

RIC-AFP-KarineP.jpg

Le RIC. Il faudra bien y venir en France

par Jean-Paul Baquiast

Ex: http://www.europesolidaire.eu

Un excellent article de Wikipédia présente le Référendum d'Initiative Citoyenne (RIC) parfois désigné du nom de Référendum d'Initiative Populaire (RIP) Nous y renvoyons le lecteur.

https://fr.wikipedia.org/wiki/R%C3%A9f%C3%A9rendum_d%27in...

En France actuellement, comme le précise l'article de Wikipédia, les Gilets jaunes proposent que le RIC soit applicable à quatre types de procédures qui existent pour partie dans certains pays mais n'existent nulle part en totalité:

  • Le référendum législatif, qui consisterait à soumettre au peuple une proposition de loi dès lors que cette proposition serait du domaine de la loi. Les citoyens inscrits sur une liste électorale et demandant un tel référendum, se verraient donner satisfaction s'ils représentaient un certain pourcentage de cette liste, par exemple 10 à 25% des inscrits.

  • Le référendum abrogatif, qui consisterait en la possibilité pour la population d'abroger ou d'empêcher la mise en application d'une loi votée précédemment par le Parlement..

  • Le référendum révocatoire, qui consisterait à démettre un élu de son mandat, qu'il ait été élu au plan local ou au plan national.

  • Le référendum constitutionnel, qui consisterait à permettre au peuple de modifier la Constitution du pays.

On objecte que ceci introduirait dans le pays concerné une telle instabilité qu'aucun gouvernement ou qu'aucune politique suivie ne serait possible. Concernant la France, il en résulterait que celle-ci, affirme-t-on, devrait renoncer à participer aux dialogues ou aux affrontements entre grandes puissances.

Elargir la base démocratique des institutions et des politiques

Le sérieux et le sens de la responsabilité qui émanent de l'essentiel des revendications des Gilets Jaunes montrent que ceux-ci, de même que les électeurs qui s'en inspireraient, seraient très soucieux de maintenir la continuité de la Nation. Ils viseraient seulement à renforcer celle-ci en lui permettant d'être gouvernée autrement que, comme c'est le cas actuellement, par les quelques 5% de citoyens super-riches et super-puissants qui depuis des années se sont attribués du pouvoir. Ils demandent seulement à donner une base populaire plus large qu'actuellement aux politiques et aux décisions appliquées par le gouvernement ou les représentants élus, pourtant supposés parler au nom du peuple et de l'intérêt général.

Il s'ensuivrait que des objectifs présentés par la majorité actuelle comme irréalistes et dangereux pourraient être abordés. Ainsi en serait-il d'une plus grande égalité des revenus ou des profits, parfaitement réalisable en quelques années sans nécessiter une révolution sociale. Parallèlement, il n'y a aucune raison de penser que les politiques présentant un intérêts vital pour le pays puissent être remises en cause. Au contraire, elles bénéficieraient d'un meilleur soutien populaire. Il en serait ainsi d'une une forte augmentation des investissements productifs ou de la part donnée aux recherches scientifiques et techniques, quelles que soient les restrictions aux dépenses de consommation qui en découleraient.

Postuler a priori et sans les avoir essayés que des RIC mettraient la France en danger montre un grand mépris de la sagesse citoyenne, celle qui s'est notamment exprimée lors des manifestations des Gilets Jaunes. Il montre surtout que l'étroite oligarchie financière et intellectuelle qui gouverne la France n'a aucune intention de partager son pouvoir.

Il est certain que dans le Grand Débat proposé par Emmanuel Macron, le RIC sera proposé. Mais il sera également certain qu'il sera refusé, car n'entrant pas dans le cadre du Débat fixé par le même Macron au service de sa politique personnelle.